Encyclopedia > Fundamental theorem of arithmetic

  Article Content

Fundamental theorem of arithmetic

The fundamental theorem of arithmetic is the statement that every positive integer can be written as a product of prime numbers in a unique way. For instance, we can write

6936 = 23 · 3 · 172   or   1200 = 24 · 3 · 52

and there are no other such factorizations of 6936 or 1200 into prime numbers, except for reorderings of the above factors.

To make the theorem work even for the number 1, we think of 1 as being the product of zero prime numbers.

Applications

Essentially, the theorem establishes the importance of prime numbers: they are the "basic building blocks" of the positive integers in that every positive integer can be put together from primes in a unique fashion.

Knowing the prime number factorization of a number gives complete knowledge about all factors of that number. For instance, the above factorization of 6936 tells us that the positive factors of 6936 are of the form

2a · 3b · 17c
with 0 ≤ a ≤ 3, 0 ≤ b ≤ 1, and 0 ≤ c ≤ 2. This yields a total of 4 · 2 · 3 = 24 positive factors.

Once the prime factorizations of two numbers are known, their greatest common divisor and least common multiple can be found quickly. For instance, from the above we see that the greatest common divisor of 6936 and 1200 is 23 · 3 = 24. However if the prime factorizations are not known, the use of Euclid's algorithm generally requires much less calculation than factoring the two numbers.

The fundamental theorem ensures that additive and multiplicative arithmetic functions are completely determined by their values on the powers of prime numbers.

Proof

The proof consists of two parts: first, we have to show that every number can indeed be written as a product of primes; then we have to show that any two such representations are essentially the same.

Suppose there were a positive integer which can not be written as a product of primes. Then there must be a smallest such number, let's call it n. This number n cannot be 1, because of our convention above. It cannot be a prime number either, since any prime number is a product of a single prime, itself. So n = ab where both a and b are positive integers smaller than n. Since n was the smallest number for which the theorem fails, both a and b can be written as products of primes. But then n = ab can be written as a product of primes as well, a contradiction.

The uniqueness part of the proof hinges on the following fact: if a prime number p divides a product ab, then it divides a or it divides b (Proof: if p doesn't divide a, then p and a are relatively prime and Bézout's identity yields integers x and y such that px + ay = 1. Multiplying with b yields pbx + aby = b. Both summands of the left-hand side are divisible by p, so the right-hand side is also divisible by p.) Now take two products of primes which are equal. Take any prime p from the first product. It divides the first product, and hence also the second. By the above fact, p must then divide at least one factor in the second product. But the factors are all primes themselves, so p must actually be equal to one of the factors of the second product. So we can cancel p from both products. Continuing in this fashion, we eventually see that the prime factors of the two products must match up precisely.



All Wikipedia text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License

 
  Search Encyclopedia

Search over one million articles, find something about almost anything!
 
 
  
  Featured Article
Lake Ronkonkoma, New York

... income for a family is $67,375. Males have a median income of $50,715 versus $34,301 for females. The per capita income for the town is $23,233. 6.2% of the population ...

 
 
 
This page was created in 24.6 ms