Encyclopedia > Copenhagen interpretation

  Article Content

Copenhagen interpretation

The Copenhagen interpretation is the mainstream interpretation of quantum mechanics; it was worked out by Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg while collaborating in Copenhagen around 1927. The interpretation attempts to answer some perplexing questions which arise as a result of the wave-particle duality in quantum mechanics.

In the classic double-slit experiment, when light passes through double slits onto a screen, alternate bands of bright and dark regions are produced. These can be explained as areas in which the light waves reinforce or cancel. However, in the late 19th century, it became experimentally apparent that light has some particle-like properties and items such as electrons have wave like properties and can also produce interference patterns.

This poses some interesting questions. Suppose one were to do the double slit experiment and reduce the light so that only one photon (or electron) passes through the slits at a time. In performing the experiment, one will see the electron or photon hit the screen one at a time. However, when one totals up where the photons have hit, one will see interference patterns that appear to be the result of interfering waves even though the experiment dealt with one particle at a time.

The questions this experiment poses are

  1. The rules of quantum mechanics tell you statistically where the particles will hit the screen, and will identify the bright bands where many particles are likely to hit and the dark bands were few particles are likely to hit. However, for a single particle, the rules of quantum mechanics cannot predict where the particle will actually be observed. What are the rules to determine where an individual particle is observed?
  2. What happens to the particle in between the time it is emitted and the time that it is observed? The particle seems to be interacting with both slits and this appears inconsistent with the behavior of a point particle, yet when the particle is observed, one sees a point particle.
  3. What causes the particle to appear to switch between statistical and non-statistical behaviors? When the particle is moving through the slits, its behavior appears to be described by a non-localized wave function which is travelling through both slits at the same time. Yet when the particle is observed it is never a diffuse non-localized wave packet, but appears to be a single point particle.

The Copenhagen interpretation answers these questions as follows:

  1. The probability statements made by quantum mechanics are irreducible in the sense that they don't just reflect our limited knowledge of some hidden variables. In classical physics, probabilities were used to describe the outcome of rolling a die, even though the process was thought to be deterministic. Probabilities were used to substitute for complete knowledge. By contrast, the Copenhagen interpretation holds that in quantum mechanics, measurement outcomes are fundamentally indeterministic.
  2. Physics is the science of outcomes of measurement processes. Speculation beyond that cannot be justified. The Copenhagen interpretation rejects questions like "where was the particle before I measured its position" as meaningless.
  3. The act of measurement causes an instantaneous "collapse of the wave function". This means that the measurement process randomly picks out exactly one of the many possibilities allowed for by the state's wave function, and the wave function instantaneously changes to reflect that pick.

Table of contents

Criticisms

The completeness of quantum mechanics (thesis 1) has been attacked by the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment which was intended to show that there have to be hidden variables in order to avoid non-local, instantaneous "effects at a distance". Bell's inequality about the measurement outcomes of such an experiment was derived on the assumption that these hidden variables exist and no non-local effects are present. In 1982, Aspect finally carried out the experiment and found Bell's inequality to be violated. This experiment has since been criticized and improved experiments have been described by Weihs and Rowe, confirming Aspect's results. These results show that interpretations which postulate locally acting hidden variables, in a sense precisely defined by Bell, are untenable.

Of the three theses above, the third is maybe the most problematic from a physicist's standpoint, because it gives a special status to measurement processes without cleanly defining them nor explaining their peculiar effects. However, in contrast to some incorrect popularizations of quantum mechanics, it is not believed that the measurement process involves consciousness. It can be demonstrated that the collapse of the wave function occurs when the wave function encounters a non-conscious measurement instrument. In fact, this characteristic of quantum mechanics has practical uses in quantum cryptography.

Many physicists and philosophers have objected to the Copenhagen interpretation, both on the grounds that it is non-deterministic and that it includes an undefined measurement process that converts probability functions into non-probabilistic measurements. Einstein's quotes "God does not play dice" and "Do you really think the moon isn't there if you aren't looking at it?" exemplify this. Schrödinger's cat was originally intended as an example to show how absurd the model was. Other physicists are even blunter; David Deutsch accuses the Copenhagen interpretation of being meaningless gibberish.

Alternatives

Many physicists have subscribed to the null interpretation of quantum mechanics summarized by Feynman's famous dictum: "Shut up and calculate!"

Since the 1980s, theoretical developments such as quantum entanglement and quantum superposition have given some support to interpretations such as the Everett many-worlds interpretation. This interpretation is preferred by some theoreticians working in fundamental physics and cosmology. Nevertheless, in the absence of observational evidence which can distinguish between Copenhagen and many-worlds, the choice between them is viewed as one of personal taste. Most physicists find this situation unsatisfactory, and the creation of experiments which can distinguish between the intepretations of quantum mechanics is an active area of research. One dramatic but highly impractical experiment that would distinguish the two is the quantum suicide experiment proposed by Max Tegmark.

Further Reading

  • G. Weihs et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 81 (1998) 5039
  • M. Rowe et al., Nature 409 (2001) 791.

External Link



All Wikipedia text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License

 
  Search Encyclopedia

Search over one million articles, find something about almost anything!
 
 
  
  Featured Article
Ludvika

... of Dalarna[?]: Avesta  |  Borlänge  |  Falun  |  Gagnef  |  Hedemora  |  Leksand  |  LudvikaMalung ...

 
 
 
This page was created in 40.7 ms