Saul Kripke (born
1940)is an
American philosopher now emeritus from (
Princeton). He is best known for his attack on the descriptivist (
Fregean,
Russellian) theory of reference with respect to
proper names, according to which a name refers to an object by virtue of the name's being associated with a description that the object in turn satisfies. He gave several examples purporting to render descriptivism implausible (e.g., surely Aristotle could have died at age 2 and so not satisfied any of the descriptions we associate with his name). Kripke proposed in descriptivism's stead a historical theory of reference, according to which a name refers to an object by virtue of its historical connection with the object as mediated through communities of speakers. Kripke also raised the prospect of
a posteriori necessities -- facts that are necessarily true, though they can be known only through empirical investigation. Examples include "Hesperus is Phosphorus", "Cicero is Tully", and other identity claims where two names refer to the same object. (These two contributions -- causal reference and a posteriori necessity -- have been echoed by
Hilary Putnam, and there is controversy as to whether Kripke was in turn echoing earlier work by
Ruth Barcan Marcus[?].) Finally, Kripke gave an argument against
identity materialism in the
philosophy of mind, the view that every mental fact is identical with some physical fact. Kripke argued that the only way to defend this identity is as an a posteriori necessary identity, but that such an identity -- e.g., pain is C-fibers firing -- could not be necessary, given the possibility of real honest-to-goodness pain that has nothing to do with C-fibers firing. Similar arguments are defended today by David Chalmers. These three contributions can be found in Kripke's lectures entitled "Naming and Necessity".
Kripke also made interesting contributions to the study of the later Wittgenstein in lectures published as Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, although his work here has been faulted for being not particularly true to the historical Wittgenstein (see e.g. Colin McGinn's Wittgenstein on Meaning) and not giving credit to other authors who interpreted Wittgenstein similarly (see e.g. Robert J. Fogelin's Wittgenstein). Kripke's influence has been substantial; much of his work, unfortunately, exists only in tape-recorded or transcript form.
Kripke also published substantial novel work in formal logic--particularly in the semantics of modal logic--while still in his teens.
All Wikipedia text
is available under the
terms of the GNU Free Documentation License