Redirected from Goedels ontological proof
St. Anselm's ontological argument, in its most succinct form, is as follows: "God, by definition, is absolute perfection. Non-existence is an imperfection. Therefore, God exists." A more elaborate version was given by Gottfried Leibniz; this is the version that Gödel studied and attempted to clarify with his ontological argument.
While Gödel was deeply religious, he never published his argument because he feared that it would be mistaken as establishing God's existence beyond doubt. Instead, he only saw it as a logical investigation and a clean formulation of Leibniz' argument with all assumptions spelled out. He repeatedly showed the argument to friends around 1970 and it was published after his death in 1987. An outline of the proof follows.
The proof uses modal logic[?] which distinguishes between necessary truths created by definitions and contingent[?] truths inferred from observations of a world.
A truth is necessary if it cannot be avoided, such as 2 + 2 = 4; by contrast, a contingent truth "just happens to be the case", for instance "more than half of the earth is covered by water". In the most common interpretation of modal logic, one considers "all possible worlds". If a statement is true in all possible worlds, then it is a necessary truth. If a statement happens to be true in our world, but is not true in all other worlds, then it is a contingent truth. A statement that is true in some world (not necessarily our own) is called a possible truth.
A property assigns to every object in every possible world a truth value (either true or false). Note that not all worlds have the same objects: some objects exist in some worlds and not in others. A property only has to assign truth values to those objects that exist in a particular world. As an example, consider the property
We say that the property P entails the property Q, if any object in any world that has the property P in that world, also has the property Q in that same world. For example, the property
As an axiom, we now assume that it is possible to single out positive properties from among all properties, and that the following three conditions hold:
Now we define a new property G: if x is an object in some possible world, then G(x) is true if and only if P(x) is true in that same world for all positive properties P. G is called the "God-like" property. An object x that has the God-like property is called a God.
One can now already show that in some world, there exists a God. But we want more: we want to show that necessarily, in every world there exists a unique God.
In order to do this, Gödel first defines essences: if x is an object in some world, then the property P is said to be an essence of x if P(x) is true in that world and if P entails all other properties that x has in that world. We also say that x strongly exists if for every essence P of x the following is true: in every possible world, there is an element y with P(y). He adds one last axiom: the property of "strongly existing" is positive.
From these hypotheses, it is now possible to prove that there is one and only one God in each world. God necessarily exists.
It was pointed out by Sobel that Gödel's axioms are too strong: they imply that all possible worlds are identical. Anderson gave a slightly different axiom system which attempts to avoid this problem.
Search Encyclopedia
|
Featured Article
|